Constrained Epistemic Extension on Agent Knowledge Acquisition

Article Preview

Abstract:

In multi-agent systems, a number of autonomous pieces of software (the agents) interact in order to execute complex tasks. This paper proposes a logic framework portrays agent’s communication protocols in the multi-agent systems and a dynamic negotiation model based on epistemic default logic was introduced in this framework. In this paper, we use the constrained default rules to investigate the extension of dynamic epistemic logic, and constrained epistemic extension construct an efficient negotiation strategy via constrained epistemic default reasoning, which guarantees the important natures of extension existence and semi-monotonicity. We also specify characteristic of the dynamic updating when agent learn new knowledge in the logical framework. The method for the information sharing signify the usefulness of logical tools carried out in the dynamic process of information acquisition, and the distributed intelligent information processing show the effectiveness of reasoning default logic in the dynamic epistemic logic theory.

You might also be interested in these eBooks

Info:

Periodical:

Pages:

943-948

Citation:

Online since:

January 2013

Export:

Price:

Permissions CCC:

Permissions PLS:

Сopyright:

© 2013 Trans Tech Publications Ltd. All Rights Reserved

Share:

Citation:

[1] R. Reiter, A Logic for default reasoning. Artificial Intelligence, vol. 13, pp.81-132, (1980).

DOI: 10.1016/0004-3702(80)90014-4

Google Scholar

[2] Pollock, J. L., Gillies, A. S. Belief revision and epistemology. Synthese 122, pp.69-92. (2000).

Google Scholar

[3] H. van Ditmarsch, W. v. d.H. a.B.K., Dynamic Epistemic Logic(Synthese Library). 2006: Springer Press.

Google Scholar

[4] Johan van Benthem, J. v.E. a.B.K., Logics of communication and change. Information and Computation, vol. 204(11), pp.1620-1662, (2006).

DOI: 10.1016/j.ic.2006.04.006

Google Scholar

[5] Antoniou, G., On the dynamics of default reasoning. International Journal of Intelligent Systems, vol. 17, pp.1143-1155, (2002).

Google Scholar

[6] W. Groeneveld, J.D.G. a., Reasoning about information change. Journal of Logic, Language, and Information, vol. 6, pp.147-169. (1997).

Google Scholar

[7] Benthem, J.V., Epistemic logic and epistemology: the state of their affairs. Philosophical Stduies, 128(5): pp.49-76. (2006).

DOI: 10.1007/s11098-005-4052-0

Google Scholar

[8] Benferhat. S, S.A., Smets. P, Belief functions and default Reasoning. Artificial Intelligence, vol. 122, pp.1-69, (2000).

DOI: 10.1016/s0004-3702(00)00041-2

Google Scholar

[9] P James, T.S., H Tompits, S Woltran, On Computing Solutions to Belief Change Scenarios. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, pp.510-540, (2001).

DOI: 10.1007/3-540-44652-4_45

Google Scholar

[10] Kaile S. Constraints on extensions on a default theory. Journal of Computer Science and Technology, vol. 16: pp.329-340, (2001).

Google Scholar

[11] Wu,M., Zhou C.L., et al. Reasoning on Constrained Epistemic Default Logic, Journal of Information and Computational Science, vol. 6(1), pp.49-55, (2009).

Google Scholar

[12] P. Liberatore. Representability in default logic. Journal of the Interest Group in Pure and Applied Logic, 13(3): 335-35, (2005).

Google Scholar

[13] Liberatore, Paolo, On the complexity of extension checking in default logic, Information Processing Letters , 98(2): pp.61-65, (2006).

DOI: 10.1016/j.ipl.2005.12.005

Google Scholar

[14] Wu,M., Zhou C.L., et al. Information update in the multi-agent system based on epistemic default logic, Journal of Information and Computational Science, vol. 6(1), pp.227-233, (2009).

Google Scholar